$title="Computation"; include_once "../prlheader.php"; ?>
We may view Nuprl as a programming language in which the proofs are programs which are ``translated'' into terms and ``run'' via an evaluator. Proving the truth of a statement in the system is equivalent to showing that the type corresponding to the statement is inhabited, and proving that a type is inhabited in a constructive setting requires that the user specify how an object of the type be built. Implicitly associated with each Nuprl proof, then, is a term whose type is specified by the main assertion being proved. This term exhibits the properties specified by the assertion it corresponds to; if we think of a programming problem as being a list of specifications, then a proof that the specifications can be met defines an algorithm which solves the problem, and the associated term becomes the computational realization of the algorithm. The system also supplies a means for evaluating these terms. Given a term the evaluator attempts to find a value corresponding to the term. For more on the correspondence between proofs and programs see [Bates & Constable 85] and [Sasaki 85].
In this chapter we consider Nuprl as a programming tool. We describe generally the way in which the system extracts terms from proofs and computes the values of terms, and we conclude the chapter with an example which demonstrates the workings of the extractor and the evaluator.
A proof gives rise to a term in that each rule used in the proof produces an extract form whose parameters are instantiated with the terms inductively extracted from the subgoals generated by the rule invocation. For example, if we wish to prove a theorem of the form using the intro rule for disjoint union we must prove either or as a subgoal. Assuming we prove and assuming is the term inductively extracted from the proof of then inr() becomes the term extracted from the proof of , for inr() is the extraction form for the right intro rule for disjoint unions. Note that if is in type then inr() is in , so the extraction makes sense. Similarly, if we prove something of the form x: » using the elim rule for disjoint union on the hypothesis, then Nuprl generates two subgoals. The first requires us to show that if is true (i.e., appears in the hypothesis list) then is true. The second requires us to show that if is true (i.e., appears in the hypothesis list) then is true. If is the term extracted from the the first subgoal ( is a term with a free variable whose type is ; recall that represents our assumption of the truth of in the first subgoal) and is the term extracted from the second subgoal, then decide() is the term extracted from the proof of x: » . Note that if corresponds to inl() for some in then from the computation rules the extracted term is equivalent to ; since proves under the assumption of and holds (since is in ) the extracted term works as desired. Similarly, the term behaves properly if has value inr() for some in ; thus this extraction form is justified.
One should note that certain standard programming constructs have analogs as Nuprl terms. In particular, recursive definition corresponds to the ind() form, which is extracted from proofs which use induction via the elim rule on integers. decide() represents a kind of if-then-else construct, while the functional terms extracted from proofs using functional intro correspond to function constructs in a standard programming language.
To display the term corresponding to a theorem one evaluates a special Nuprl term, term_of(), which constructs the extracted term of in a recursive fashion. Briefly, the extraction form of the top refinement rule becomes the outermost form of the term being constructed. The parameters of the form then become the terms constructed from the subgoals generated by the refinement rule.
Many Nuprl rules require the user to prove that a type is well-formed, i.e., that the type resides in some universe . These subgoals, when proved, yield the extraction term axiom and are usually ignored by term_of as it builds the term for a theorem.
We should note here that one can manipulate canonical and noncanonical terms explicitly in the system. For example, the following definition defines an absolute value function.
abs(<x:int>) == less (<x>; 0; -<x>; <x>)We may now use abs as a definition in the statement and proof of theorems. This capability adds a great deal of flexibility to the system.
A given term may contain many noncanonical subterms, so some strategy for choosing the subterm to be reduced is essential. It may not be necessary to reduce all the noncanonical subterms, as a canonical term can contain noncanonical subterms. The strategy chosen is a lazy strategy in that it chooses a minimal number of reductions needed to reduce the term to canonical form. The evaluator cannot always succeed since there are terms which have no canonical form. However, the evaluator will succeed on any term which can be assigned a type.
For example, suppose we have a theorem named bruce with main goal
>> x:int -> y:int # (x=y in int)proved so that the extracted term is x.<x,axiom>. We could have the following session with the evaluator.
... ... |P>eval | |E>let p1 = \x.spread(x;u,v.u);; | |\x.spread(x;u,v.u) | |E>let t = term_of(bruce);; | |\x.<x,axiom> | |E>t(17);; | |<17,axiom> | |E>p1(t(17));; | |17 | ... ...
The Nuprl command create eval creates a library object that can contain any number of bindings (all terminated by ;;). The library objects created in this way are edited using ted and so may contain def refs. Checking an EVAL object augments the EVAL environment by evaluating the bindings it contains. All EVAL objects in a library are evaluated when the library is loaded.
Thm1 >>all x:int. square(x) | ~ square(x). Thm2 >>all x:int. square(x) vel ~ square(x).The first theorem can be proved by introducing and applying the rootf function to . We can prove that either rootf(x)*rootf(x)=x in int or not by using the arithmetic rule, arith; the proof yields a decision procedure identifying which case holds. From a proof of Thm1, then, we can extract a function which will decide whether an integer is a square, namely x.decide(term_of(Thm1)(x); u.0;v.1). This function gives if is a square and otherwise.
The second theorem has a trivial proof. We simply use the fact that vel ~ holds for any proposition and take rootf(x)*rootf(x)=x in int as . However, there is no interesting computational content to this result; we do not obtain from it a procedure to decide whether is a square. (The interested reader should prove this theorem and display its computational content.)
The following is a small proof in Nuprl with the extraction clauses shown explicitly. The system does not produce the comments (* *); we include them for illustrative purposes only. In the interest of condensing the presentation we also elide hypothesis lists wherever possible.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top (* term_of(thm) extracted *) | |>> all x,y:int.(x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y | | in int | | | |BY quantifier (* ext \x.\y.e1 (quantifier tactic does | | intro twice) *) | |1* 1. x:(int) | | 2. y:(int) | | >> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int))| | (* ext e1 *) | |2* >> (int) in U1 | | | |3* >> (int) in U1 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
The rule quantifier is a tactic, a user-defined rule of inference, which successively applies the intro rule to each universal quantifier; in this case it performs two applications. This tactic was written by a user of the system and must be loaded as an ML object to be used; in general it would not be available. See the following chapter for more on tactics. The extracted term is a function which, given any values for and , will give a proof of the body; this corresponds to the intuitive meaning of all and justifies its definition as a dependent function. Note that is the term extracted from the first subgoal; the next window shows the proof of this subgoal.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 (* e1 extracted *) | |1...2. | |>> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int)) | | | |BY seq (x=y in int)|~(x=y in int) new E (* ext \E.e3(e2) *) | | | |1* 1...2. | | >> (x=y in int)|~(x=y in int) (* ext e2 *) | | | |2* 1...2. | | 3. E:(x=y in int)|~(x=y in int) | | >> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int))| | (* ext e3 *) | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
The seq rule extracts a function which in effect substitutes the proof of the seq term, , for each instance of its use in (under the name E).
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 1 (* e2 extracted *) | |1...2. | |>> (x=y in int)|~(x=y in int) | | | |BY arith (* ext int_eq(x;y;inl(axiom);inr(axiom)) *) | | | |1* 1...2. | | >> x in int | | | |2* 1...2. | | >> y in int | | | |3* 1...2. | | >> x in int | | | |4* 1...2. | | >> y in int | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
The arith decision procedure produces the int_eq term, a decision procedure for equality on the integers.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 (* e3 extracted *) | |1...2. | |3. E:(x=y in int)|~(x=y in int) | |>> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int)) | | | |BY elim 3 (* ext decide(E;l.e4;r.e5) *) | | | |1* 1...3. | | 4. l:(x=y in int) | | >> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int))| | (* ext e4 *) | |2* 1...3. | | 4. r:~(x=y in int) | | >> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int))| | (* ext e5 *) | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
The elim rule for disjoint unions produces a decide term. In the next frame the term l is extracted from the first subgoal because our goal is exactly l (the actual proof of this subgoal is not shown but is carried out using the rule hyp 4).
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 1 (* e4 extracted *) | |1...3. | |4. l:(x=y in int) | |>> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int)) | | | |BY intro left (* ext inl(e6) *) | | | |1* 1...4. | | >> (x=y in int) (* ext e6==l (follows by hyp 4) *) | | | |2* 1...4. | | >> some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int) in U1 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
In the next frame r is extracted for the same reason as l is above.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 2 (* e5 extracted *) | |1...3. | |4. r:~(x=y in int) | |>> ((x=y in int)|some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int)) | | | |BY intro right (* ext inr(e7) *) | | | |1* 1...4. | | >> some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int) (ext e7 *) | | | |2* 1...4. | | >> ((x=y in int)) in U1 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
In the next frame, since some is defined to be a dependent product we extract a pair consisting of an element of the integers, y-x, and a proof, e8, that the proposition is true for this element. This corresponds to the desired meaning of some.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 2 1 (* e7 extracted *) | |1...3. | |4. r:~(x=y in int) | |>> some z:int.~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int) | | | |BY intro y-x (* ext <y-x,e8> *) | | | |1* 1...4. | | >> y-x in (int) | | | |2* 1...4. | | >> ((y-x=0 in int)->void)#(x+y-x=y in int) (* ext e8 *)| | | |3* 1...4. | | 5. z:(int) | | >> (~(z=0 in int)#(x+z=y in int)) in U1 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
The product intro produces a pair consisting of proofs of the two subgoals. Although the proof is not shown here, subgoal 2 can be seen to follow trivially by arith.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 2 1 2 (* e8 extracted *) | |1...3. | |4. r:~(x=y in int) | |>> ((y-x=0 in int)->void)#(x+y-x=y in int) (* ext <e9,e10>*)| | | |BY intro | | | |1* 1...4. | | >> (y-x=0 in int)->void (* ext e9 *) | | | |2* 1...4. | | >> x+y-x=y in int (* ext e10==axiom (follows by arith)*)| '------------------------------------------------------------' |
In the next frame we see that hypotheses 4 and 5 contradict each other. The system somewhat arbitrarily extracts (v0.any(v0))(r(axiom)) from this (we could extract anything we desired from a contradiction).
,------------------------------------------------------------, |EDIT THM thm | |------------------------------------------------------------| |* top 1 2 2 1 2 1 (* e9 extracted *) | |1...3. | |4. r:~(x=y in int) | |>> (y-x=0 in int)->void | | | |BY intro new f (* ext \f.e11 *) | | | |1* 1...4. | | 5. f:y-x=0 in int | | >> void (* ext e11==(\v0.any(v0))(r(axiom)) | | (from a contradiction)*)| | | |2* 1...4. | | >> (y-x=0 in int) in U1 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
We could now have the following session with the evaluator. What follows has additional white space (spaces and carriage returns) to improve readability.
,------------------------------------------------------------, |P>eval | |E>term_of(thm);; | |\x.\y.(\E.decide(E;l.inl(l); | | r.inr(<y-x,<\f.(\v0.any(v0))(r(axiom)),axiom>>))) | | (int_eq(x;y ;inl(axiom);inr(axiom))) | |E>term_of(thm)(7)(7);; | |inl(axiom) | |E>term_of(thm)(7)(10);; | |inr(<10-7,<\f.(\v0.any(v0))(axiom(axiom)),axiom>>) | |E>let p1 = \x.spread(x;u,v.u);; | |\x.spread(x;u,v.u) | |E>let d = \y.decide(y;u.p1(u);u.p1(u));; | |\y.decide(y;u.p1(u);u.p1(u)) | |E>d(term_of(thm)(7)(10));; | |3 | '------------------------------------------------------------' |
To terminate an eval session type .